Seth wrote:[
The Court said of this: "Logically, of course, a legitimate state interest in this area need not stand or fall on acceptance of the belief that life begins at conception or at some other point prior to live birth. In assessing the State's interest, recognition may be given to the less rigid claim that as long as at least potential life is involved, the State may assert interests beyond the protection of the pregnant woman alone. Source: Roe v. Wade."
My point exactly. The issue doesn't have anything to do with "when life begins." A legitimate state interest need not stand or fall on the belief that life begins at conception or at some other point prior to live birth. It can stand or fall at some other point.
But, anyway, the context of that quote is very important. It's in section VII of the court's opinion which says: "Three reasons have been advanced to explain historically the enactment of criminal abortion laws in the 19th century and to justify their continued existence.....The third reason is the State's interest-some phrase it in terms of duty-in protecting prenatal life. Some of the argument for this justification rests on the theory that a new human life is present from the moment of conception. 45 The State's interest and general obligation to protect life then extends, it is argued, to prenatal life. Only when the life of the pregnant mother herself is at stake, balanced against the life she carries within her, should the interest of the embryo or fetus not prevail. Logically, of course, a legitimate state interest in this area need not stand or fall on acceptance of the belief that life begins at conception or at some other point prior to live birth. In assessing the State's interest, recognition may be given to the less rigid claim that as long as at least potential life is involved, the State may assert interests beyond the protection of the pregnant woman alone. [410 U.S. 113, 151].... It is with these interests, and the weight to be attached to them, that this case is concerned."
So, the court is expounding upon the reasons and justifications advanced for criminalizing abortions, and is telling the reader that the case is about these alleged interests and the weight to be accorded them. It's not a holding or a finding.
Seth wrote:
The Court also said, in reference to the definition of "persons," "But in nearly all these instances, the use of the word is such that it has application only post-natally. None indicates, with any assurance, that it has any possible pre-natal application.
The error here is that the Court deliberately chooses a narrow interpretation of "person" based only on the Constitution, but fails to acknowledge that the Texas legislature is competent to define a "person" for the purposes of a state regulation in a manner that is broader, but not narrower than the definition found in the 14th Amendment.
In federal constitutional interpretation, the definition of "person" is a function of federal constitutional law, not state law. If every state could define "person" differently than the federal constitution could mean something different in every state.
Moreover, here is the context of your quote:
A. The appellee and certain amici argue that the fetus is a "person" within the language and meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment. In support of this, they outline at length and in detail the well-known facts of fetal development. If this suggestion of personhood is established, the appellant's case, of course, collapses, for the fetus' right to life would then be guaranteed specifically by the Amendment. The appellant conceded as much on reargument. 51 On the other hand, the appellee conceded on reargument 52 that no case could be cited that holds that a fetus is a person within the meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment.
The Constitution does not define "person" in so many words. Section 1 of the Fourteenth Amendment contains three references to "person." The first, in defining "citizens," speaks of "persons born or naturalized in the United States." The word also appears both in the Due Process Clause and in the Equal Protection Clause. "Person" is used in other places in the Constitution: in the listing of qualifications for Representatives and Senators, Art. I, § 2, cl. 2, and § 3, cl. 3; in the Apportionment Clause, Art. I, § 2, cl. 3; 53 in the Migration and Importation provision, Art. I, § 9, cl. 1; in the Emolument Clause, Art. I, § 9, cl. 8; in the Electors provisions, Art. II, § 1, cl. 2, and the superseded cl. 3; in the provision outlining qualifications for the office of President, Art. II, § 1, cl. 5; in the Extradition provisions, Art. IV, § 2, cl. 2, and the superseded Fugitive Slave Clause 3; and in the Fifth, Twelfth, and Twenty-second Amendments, as well as in §§ 2 and 3 of the Fourteenth Amendment. But in nearly all these instances, the use of the word is such that it has application only postnatally. None indicates, with any assurance, that it has any possible pre-natal application. 54
All this, together with our observation, supra, that throughout the major portion of the 19th century prevailing legal abortion practices were far freer than they are today, persuades us that the word "person," as used in the Fourteenth Amendment, does not include the unborn.
The court expounded on the history of the meaning of the word "person" in the Constitution. It didn't include the unborn.
Seth wrote:
Section one says:
Section 1. All persons born or naturalized in the United States, and subject to the jurisdiction thereof, are citizens of the United States and of the State wherein they reside. No State shall make or enforce any law which shall abridge the privileges or immunities of citizens of the United States; nor shall any State deprive any person of life, liberty, or property, without due process of law; nor deny to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws.
This Amendment, which extends all Constitutional rights to "persons" born or naturalized, was designed to make sure that slaves, who were previously not "persons" under the Constitution, had rights. But this is the federal MINIMUM standard for the enjoyment of rights. Nothing prevents (or is supposed to prevent) a STATE from providing BROADER rights or BROADER descriptions of "persons" than the Constitution does.
Nothing allows the States to individually define terms within the Constitution. A State can't, for example, define what "speech" is. That's a federal Cosntitutional matter. The 14th Amendment applies to federal "persons" and states that States may not deprive persons of life, liberty, or property. There is nothing that says that the a State can broaden the definition of "person" and, say, include dogs and cats as "persons" for 14th amendment purposes and then allow them rights equal to humans.
Seth wrote:
What the Court did, which is rather novel, is to deliberately DENY a living human being constitutional protections that were extended to that being by a state legislature. That's a violation of state sovereignty.
The 14th Amendment is inherently a violation of State sovereignty, so of course. Any limitation on the State's power to legislate is a limitation on its sovereignty. That's what the 14th Amendment does and what it was intended to do.
Seth wrote:
While Texas is forbidden to infringe upon the rights of constitutionally-defined "persons" (which includes former slaves) by treating them as "non-persons," and the Constitution has been likewise seen to protect even non-citizen "persons" in the corpus of illegal aliens and Texas may not treat them as "non-persons," the Court abused its authority by overruling a legitimate act of the Texas legislature which extended the protections of "personhood" to the fetus. The Courts are supposed to defer to the elected representatives of the People unless their action infringes upon some superior constitutional right.
...the woman's right to privacy. But, no, the Court's are not to "defer, unless..." - they are to interpret and apply the Constitution, and if a state law violates the 14th Amendment, then it is struck down.
Seth wrote:
Note that the Court did not say "a fetus is not a person," it pettifogged and obfuscated around that fundamental issue by saying that:
"All this, together with our observation, supra, that, throughout the major portion of the 19th century, prevailing legal abortion practices were far freer than they are today, persuades us that the word "person," as used in the Fourteenth Amendment, does not include the unborn."
But that was not the issue before the Court in this particular point. The issue before the Court was, or should have been, does Texas law define a fetus as a "person?" Since the definition of "person" insofar as Texas' constitutional authority to make law is not a matter that in and of itself impacts any constitutional right, it does not fall under the strict scrutiny requirements, and the Court was obliged to respect Texas' definition if there was a rational basis for that legislative decision.
With all due respect to what you think "should have been" the issue before the Court, the Court rendered its opinion on the issues before it.
And, the Court did find that Texas violated a fundamental right.
Seth wrote:
But the Court recognized that if Texas was permitted to define a fetus as a "person," it's machinations and rationalizations regarding the right of privacy of the mother would be severely damaged, so it departed from good jurisprudence and "made law" itself by artificially (and for the first time since the 14th Amendment was ratified) narrowing the scope of protection of the 14th Amendment by excluding fetuses from its protections.
And the essential question is, by what authority did the Supreme Court overrule the sovereign judgment of the Texas legislature in broadening the protections of the state and federal Constitutions to another class of "persons?"
Again, the State legislature does not have the power to define and re-define the terms used in the federal Constitution. That's a matter of federal Constitutional law. Using your logic, the State can define a fetus as person today, and then when the liberals take the State legislature next year, they can define the fetus as not a person, and we can ping pong back and forth. And, all 50 states would have the same right, so by crossing the State lines, the fetus in a woman's uterus would have federal constitutional rights in State X, lose them in State Y, and gain them back again in State Z, depending on the vicissitudes of the State legislature.
You've got that part wrong, and it is the foundation of your entire argument.
Seth wrote:
It's one thing to say that a woman's right of privacy is founded in the 14th and 9th Amendments, but it's quite another to say that a state is not authorized to more stringently protect the rights of a class of individuals defined as fetuses by extending constitutional protections to them. That's an action more in harmony with the Dred Scott decision that denied "personhood" and humanity to slaves than it is modern, enlightened jurisprudence.
A State could not say that Gorilla's were persons, and then bind the entire US in doing so, and the meaning of the term person in the 14th Amendment can't include Gorillas in Texas, Chimpanzees in Washington, and neither of them in Idaho, and unborn gorillas in Ohio. Again, the States don't get to define the word "person" for the purposes of the federal constitution. They may have a definition of the word person for the purposes of State law, but they can't, for example, define an appendix as a "person" and then the rights of born humans are thereby extended to appendixes in that State. Your logic would require that States have that power.
Seth wrote:
And in fact the Court did not end up simply making fetuses "non-persons," in fact it took the opposite tack shortly later in ruling that the woman's right to privacy is not absolute, and that the state does have a legitimate interest in preserving a fetus in the third trimester.
Yes - a State's legitimate interests do not rest exclusively on when life begins. The court said that explicitly.
Seth wrote:
So, here's the dichotomy: By what legal authority does the Supreme Court determine when a fetus becomes a "person" in the law?
The United States Constitution under Article III, wherein the SCOTUS is the Supreme Court of the land, and has the authority to interpret and apply the Constitution of the United States. That means that the SCOTUS will define what "free speech" is and what "religion" is and what a "person" is and what a "citizen" is. States don't get to redefine "religion" - that has a meaning under federal Constitutional law as found by the SCOTUS. Similarly, it's up to the SCOTUS to interpret the meaning of the word "person."
Your logic would allow for the following - two cases are filed, one in State X and one in State Y, challenging the abortion law. State X defines the fetus as a person from conception, and State Y defines it from birth. All other facts are the same. The Court would have to defer to the States, and render two rulings - one would be that the same law is Constitutional under the US constitution in State X and unconstitutional in State Y, and a 14th Amendment person is something different in each State.
Seth wrote:
That is the duty of the legislature, not the courts.
It is the duty of the Court to interpret the meaning of the words used in the 14th Amendment and elsewhere in the federal Constitution. It is not the duty of State legislatures to define those terms.
Seth wrote:
Courts are supposed to be restricted to making determinations of law based on legislative acts. The legislature passes a law, and the Court decides if that law complies with the Constitution.
Yes. And, the Court found that the Texas law in Roe v Wade did not comply with the US Constitution.
Seth wrote:
In this case, in addition to determining that the Texas law violated the privacy rights of Roe, which was a legitimate judicial act, the Court went far beyond its legal authority to make a legislative determination as to when a fetus becomes a "person" in the law. That is a clear usurpation of the power of the legislature and the Separation of Powers Doctrine, and it's reversible error.
Actually, no. The court said of the "person" issue: "This conclusion, however, does not of itself fully answer the contentions raised by Texas, and we pass on to other considerations."
Texas urges that, apart from the Fourteenth Amendment, life begins at conception and is present throughout pregnancy, and that, therefore, the State has a compelling interest in protecting that life from and after conception. We need not resolve the difficult question of when life begins. When those trained in the respective disciplines of medicine, philosophy, and theology are unable to arrive at any consensus, the judiciary, at this point in the development of man's knowledge, is not in a position to speculate as to the answer.
In view of all this, we do not agree that, by adopting one theory of life, Texas may override the rights of the pregnant woman that are at stake. We repeat, however, that the State does have an important and legitimate interest in preserving and protecting the health of the pregnant woman, whether she be a resident of the State or a nonresident who seeks medical consultation and treatment there, and that it has still another important and legitimate interest in protecting the potentiality of human life. These interests are separate and distinct. Each grows in substantiality as the woman approaches term and, at a point during pregnancy, each becomes "compelling."
The SCOTUS is basically saying, "we aren't going say when life begins, but we acknowledge that the woman has privacy rights in her own body, and the State has interests both in protecting the mother's life and health, and protecting EVEN THE POTENTIALITY OF LIFE. And, the court alludes to the sliding scale that is the trimester rule when it says "each grows in substantiality as the woman approaches term and at a point during pregnancy each becomes compelling.
The Court went on to say:
With respect to the State's important and legitimate interest in the health of the mother, the "compelling" point, in the light of present medical knowledge, is at approximately the end of the first trimester. This is so because of the now-established medical fact, referred to above at 149, that until the end of the first trimester mortality in abortion may be less than mortality in normal childbirth. It follows that, from and after this point, a State may regulate the abortion procedure to the extent that the regulation reasonably relates to the preservation and protection of maternal health. Examples of permissible state regulation in this area are requirements as to the qualifications of the person who is to perform the abortion; as to the licensure of that person; as to the facility in which the procedure is to be performed, that is, whether it must be a hospital or may be a clinic or some other place of less-than-hospital status; as to the licensing of the facility; and the like.
This means, on the other hand, that, for the period of pregnancy prior to this "compelling" point, the attending physician, in consultation with his patient, is free to determine, without regulation by the State, that, in his medical judgment, the patient's pregnancy should be terminated. If that decision is reached, the judgment may be effectuated by an abortion free of interference by the State.
With respect to the State's important and legitimate interest in potential life, the "compelling" point is at viability. This is so because the fetus then presumably has the capability of meaningful life outside the mother's womb. State regulation protective of fetal life after viability thus has both logical and biological justifications. If the State is interested in protecting fetal life after viability, it may go so far as to proscribe abortion during that period, except when it is necessary to preserve the life or health of the mother.
Measured against these standards, Art. 1196 of the Texas Penal Code, in restricting legal abortions to those "procured or attempted by medical advice for the purpose of saving the life of the mother," sweeps too broadly. The statute makes no distinction between abortions performed early in pregnancy and those performed later, and it limits to a single reason, "saving" the mother's life, the legal justification for the procedure. The statute, therefore, cannot survive the constitutional attack made upon it here.
No issue of when "life" begins. The Court ruled based only on the State's interests - in the first trimester, there is no compelling interest. In the second trimester and beyond the State begins to have a compelling interest, but that interest is to regulate abortions to protect the mother. After viability, the State has a compelling interest in protecting the unborn.
Seth wrote:
The Court simply evaded the objective science, which clearly demonstrates that "life" begins when the zygote is formed, by reciting a litany of historical practices and ignoring advances in medical knowledge, while at the same time making an entirely arbitrary distinction that the state may regulate abortion in the 2nd trimester for reasons of maternal health, but in the third trimester in order to preserve the "life" of the fetus, without ever acknowledging the scientific facts involved.
Life actually begins when the sperm and egg are formed in the gonads of the parents. Sperm are alive, and eggs are alive. And, they are human. Yet, I kill millions of them almost daily.
And those are parts of your body, so you may do so. But when the sperm and egg unite and the parental chromosomes align along the spindle apparatus, embryologists universally agree that the first cell of the new, unique, living human organism comes into existence. This is the only important metric in this discussion. When does a NEW HUMAN LIFE begin? [/quote]
That is not universally agreed, and the Court addressed the fact that medical science has not been uniform as to when human life begins, and the court also said that it does not matter for the purposes of its decision. YOU want it to be about when when life begins. The Court explained quite clearly that it wasn't making that determination and that it was finding that the State can even have an interest when POTENTIAL human life exists.
Seth wrote:
The trimester idea is not based on the idea of life beginning at a certain time - it is instead a balancing of fundamental rights that are coming into conflict and the interest of the State.
Correct, but the Court cannot balance the fundamental rights of a non-person, now can it? If it's not a "person," then there is no need to balance any rights at all. Indeed, that was the argument of several of the amici in the case, who argued that until birth, a woman's right to terminate a pregnancy is absolute.
I should have said the Court declined to find that a fetus is a person, and declined to rule on when human life begins, because neither of those questions were necessary to its decision. The Court did find that the woman is a person, and that the State has different and distinct compelling interests that change during the course of the pregnancy, and that's what the trimester rule recognizes.
Seth wrote:
But implicit in the decision is the acknowledgment that at some point during gestation a "person" exists that the state has an interest in protecting.
The Court noted that the State can have a compelling interest in protecting non-persons - "potential" human life. You're missing it. The State's compelling interest is what allows it to violate or limit a fundamental right. In this case, the woman's fundamental right to privacy can be violated after viability, because the State has a compelling state interest in preserving potential life after that point.
Seth wrote:
The Court was deliberately vague about when this point of demarcation occurs, but obviously it occurs at some point. The logical question that follows is why is one point any more or less valid than any other point?
The Court wasn't really vague at all - first trimester, no interest in the State to prohibit abortions. Second trimester, State has a compelling interest to protect the health of the mother and may regulate abortions to that extent. After viability, then the compelling interest to protect the fetus attaches.
Seth wrote:
Legally speaking, the 14th Amendment says that all "persons" are protected in their right to life, and if the fetus is a "person" at any point during gestation, then it has rights that must be protected. The Court acknowledged that this is the case,
It did not acknowledge that fetus was a person. It said that if a fetus was a person under the 14th Amendment, then the ruling would be different.
Seth wrote:
but refused to be more specific about when those rights attach. What they did, explicitly, is leave the decision up to the states to decide when a fetus is to be protected, at least in the second and third trimesters.
Except that those protections must further the compelling State interests involved. See above.
Seth wrote:
But this "balancing of rights" is an equivocation of the requirements of the 14th Amendment and the individual's right to life because it fails to provide any objective basis to decide at what point a fetus becomes a "person" while insisting that at some point, it does become a person. They leave that up to the states to decide, but they restrict that authority by prohibiting them from banning abortion in the first trimester.
The Court did not say that the fetus does at some point become a person in utero.
Seth wrote:
So once again we have a tension between state sovereignty and constitutional interpretation. The Court says to Texas, "You may consider a fetus a person at some arbitrary point in the second or third trimester, but you may not extend the protections of the Constitution to a fetus in the first trimester."
No, the court said Texas can't infringe on the rights of the mother to have an abortion in the first trimester (whether or not the fetus is alive), and Texas can limit the right to abortion in the second trimester insofar as that limitation furthers the compelling state interest of protecting the life and health of the motioner (whether or not the fetus is alive), and that Texas could regulate and prohibit abortions after viability to further the compelling state interest of protecting even the potentiality of human life. These changing interests recognize the biology of fetal development.
Seth wrote:
This raises the question of what authority the court has to CONSTRAIN a state legislature's broadening of constitutional protections?
The authority to interpret and apply the US Constitution. I addressed this above.
Seth wrote:
It's kind of like the rule that if Joe is on a bridge and sees Bill hanging by his fingertips pleading to be helped up. Even if Joe entails 0 risk to himself, he is not obliged to pull Bill up. He can walk away, and has every right to do so, even if Bill dies. Bill has a right to life, but that right does not overcome Joe's liberty to do as he pleases, and Joe can't be compelled to help Bill.
In the womb, a fetus is interfering with the mother's rights - early on in the pregnancy, the fetus not very developed with no sentience, etc., and cannot survive outside of the mother. So, the mother's rights are said to outweigh the fetuses' rights. And, the State's interest in preserving life at that stage is relatively low. Later in the pregnancy, the State's interest in protecting life attaches, and the fetus, which is almost a born baby. It's a balancing test, not a black-and-white - is it life or is it not life - issue.
The problem with that argument is that it disregards the constitutional protections afforded to all persons,
Fetus has not been found to be a 14th Amendment person.
Seth wrote:
which does not distinguish between the convenience of one person and the life of another person. The imposition on the mother's rights is an imposition on her convenience or comfort (absent some legitimate threat to her life) while the imposition on the fetus is its death. That's not a "balancing" of anything in the estimation of many people. You also disregard the duty and obligation the mother took on by voluntarily having sex, which is a known factor in pregnancy. That voluntary act, in the opinion of many, substantially reduces the "interference" justification.
Your opinion is noted.
Seth wrote:
The Court acknowledged that if "life" begins at conception, or rather, as biology tells us, at the formation of the zygote, about 24 hours after fertilization, then that person's life would be protected by the 14th Amendment.
"The appellee and certain amici argue that the fetus is a "person" within the language and meaning of the Fourteenth Amendment. In support of this, they outline at length and in detail the well known facts of fetal development. If this suggestion of personhood is established, the appellant's case, of course, collapses, for the fetus' right to life would then be guaranteed specifically by the Amendment. The appellant conceded as much on reargument." Source: Roe V. Wade
Therefore, instead of acceding to the wisdom of the state legislatures, whose duty it is to balance the rights of the fetus and the rights of the mother in making laws that reflect the needs and desires of the residents of the states, the Court chose to make law itself, which is called "judicial activism" and is generally reversible error, instead of granting the usual substantial deference to both state legislatures and state high courts in determining the breadth of a woman's "right to privacy" and a fetus' "right to life."
You're actually misstating it. There is no rule of "deference" to state legislatures and state courts on FEDERAL rights.
That's the problem.[/quote]
Then push to amend the Constitution.
Seth wrote:
The Court had to concoct a "federal right" in order to have jurisdiction in the first place.
14th Amendment was ratified, not concocted.
Seth wrote:
Their arguments regarding privacy are exceedingly strained and grasping. And it also had to disrespect the rights of the fetus to get to its conclusion.
Your opinion is noted. I find the opinion as rational and rendering a reasonable opinion in a difficult case with no completely satisfying solution.
Seth wrote:
Clearly this was a political decision and an act of judicial lawmaking, not a proper exercise of judicial power.
That's not at all "clear," but your opinion is noted.
Seth wrote:
Note, also, the court's use of the term "personhood" and not "life."
Note that the court uses "life" on numerous occasions, including in reference to a state's interest in protecting a fetus in the 2nd and 3rd trimester.
Sure - the Court said that the state may have a compelling interest even in protecting potential life, and it made no determination as to if/when a fetus, like Peter Frampton, comes alive.
Seth wrote:
Seth wrote:
The reasoning used to justify this intrusion on state's rights is weak at best, and consists primarily of a historical review of past practice that utterly ignores the fact that the whole purpose of a legislature is to make laws that serve the present needs of the community, even when those laws differ from past practice. For example, drunk driving was once a mitigating factor in an accident, but now it's an aggravating factor.
It's an interpretation of the 14th Amendment which is itself the biggest intrusion into states rights that has ever occurred. It limits what States may deprive their citizens of, and it has a substantive aspect and procedural aspect. Substantively, the State may not deprive a person of a fundamental liberty without a compelling state interest and by means narrowly tailored to effectuate that interest without going beyond that interest or the necessary means. The woman has rights, and those rights include the right to privacy which is found to be implied in the Constitution (and/or within the "penumbra" of other rights) - it's the same right that affords a woman (or man) a fundamental right to take birth control.
But it deprives the fetus of fundamental liberties by defining it as a non-person in the first trimester.
And, the court explained the litany of precedent for a fetus not being a person.
Seth wrote:
Moreover, it deprives the states of their sovereign right to define a fetus as a person and extend protection to the fetus.
Already addressed - the States don't have the "sovereign right" to define what "person" means in the 14th amendment any more than they have the right to define what "liberty" means. That's a function of federal Constitutional law and is in the purview of the SCOTUS to decide what those words mean.
Seth wrote:
The question becomes whether or not a woman's right to privacy is outweighed by the fetus' right to live,
That's the question you'd LIKE it to become. But, that's not the question. The question is whether the State has a compelling state interest to interfere with the woman's fundamental right. The SCOTUS found that it did not in the first trimester, and it did in the second trimester (to protect the mother), and it did after viability (to protect the potentiality of human life).
Seth wrote:
and the state's right to protect it. Given the weak nature of the woman's right to privacy, and the deadly consequences to the fetus, many people believe the court struck the wrong, and indeed an illegal balance.
Your belief is noted. You've not shown "illegal" balance, because you've merely asserted some State "sovereign right" to define the words in the federal Constitution on an ad hoc state-by-state basis. That right has never existed.